The buzzword “antifascism”
The Trump administration wants to combat leftwing extremism significantly more in the wake of the Charlie Kirk shooting. The term that is being thrown around is “antifascists” or “antifa”. Per the government’s argument, leftwing individuals and networks justify violence by claiming it is the only viable way of fighting existing fascist structures or preventing a full-blown fascist dictatorship.
The left’s position is outrage over the perceived ban of all opposition to fascism. We are really dealing with two different concepts and different legal frameworks:
- General opposition to fascism
- Marxist-leninist antifascism
Almost everyone who cherishes constitutional government, civil equality, and basic human rights feels in some sense anti‑fascist. Americans are not imperial British subjects. Fascism has the same basic Roman imperial structures and methods as European aristocratic empires. A notable difference is that leading aristocratic supercluster-dynasties were at least 1200 years old and a closed-off network. Modern fascism in Italy and Germany simply deleted aristocratic heritage as a must-have. Mussolini cared not so much about what people looked like. Hitler was fanatical about it.
There is a broad, pluralist resistance to authoritarian ultranationalism—a civic defense mounted by liberals, conservatives, social democrats, religious groups, and non‑Marxist socialists who insist that the rule of law and individual rights are non‑negotiable. The other phenomenon is Marxist‑Leninist antifascism, a tactical banner that subordinates the anti‑fascist struggle to the strategic objective of socialist revolution and one‑party rule. In practice, this Leninist “antifascism” has usually ended in the establishment of police states that wield systematic violence long after open fascist threats have passed.
This essay distinguishes these two projects along four axes—ends, means, institutions, and law—and then traces the historical record: the Bolshevik template; the Spanish Civil War; the post‑1945 “people’s democracies” of Central and Eastern Europe; and the German Democratic Republic’s self‑branding as an “antifascist” state. It then compares two legal regimes: (1) West Germany’s 1956 ban of the Communist Party (KPD) under a constitutional doctrine of “defensive democracy,” and (2) the current legal framework in the United States under the Trump administration for combating extremist left groups and individuals. Throughout, the theme is consistent: general, pluralist anti‑fascism seeks to defend a constitutional order, while Marxist‑Leninist antifascism treats that order as the obstacle to be overthrown—either in a storm of revolution or by a “peaceful” takeover that culminates, inevitably, in coercive one‑party rule.
I. What Is General, Pluralist Anti‑Fascism?
1) Ends: Preservation of the Constitutional Order
General anti‑fascism is defensive and preservative. It aims to keep open the space of constitutional politics—elections, independent courts, a free press, protected opposition, and non‑violent contestation. It is not inherently tied to any single social theory of history. Liberals emphasize individual rights; Christian democrats stress the moral law; conservatives point to ordered liberty. Social democrats add a solidaristic ethic to temper markets. None of these, however, make the abolition of constitutional constraints a precondition of victory over fascism. Their idea of “winning” is to ensure that the constitutional republic survives—and improves.
2) Means: Coalition, Persuasion, Non‑Violence Under Law
Non‑Marxist anti‑fascism relies on coalitions and legal instruments. It uses elections, legislation, policing under judicial oversight, and civic organization. Resistance movements under fascist occupation sometimes fought with arms; but where the constitutional state is intact, general anti‑fascism insists on the rule of law and rejects the logic of permanent revolutionary violence as self‑defeating.
3) Institutions: Rights First, Parties Second
General anti‑fascism accepts party competition under a superior constitutional framework. Parties are tools; rights are foundations. An anti‑fascist coalition that destroys free elections or independent courts in order to win has already become something else.
4) Law: Defensive, Not Transformational
The legal imagination here is defensive: to criminalize violence and conspiracy; to police parties that abandon democratic methods; to preserve equal protection while preventing the abuse of freedoms to annihilate freedom itself. When democracies enact special measures (party bans, emergency statutes), they aim at proportionate defense—not at total social transformation.
II. What Is Marxist‑Leninist “Antifascism”?
1) Ends: The Dictatorship of the Proletariat
Marxism‑Leninism reads fascism as the final, terroristic stage of capitalist rule. In this framework, fascism is not an aberration but the mask that finance capital dons when parliamentary tricks can no longer protect class power. Consequently, defeating fascism within a bourgeois republic is, for Leninists, never the final goal. The goal is to abolish the bourgeois state and replace it with the “dictatorship of the proletariat”—which in practice means the unchallengeable rule of a vanguard party.
2) Means:
Two tracks, same destination.
Track A: Insurrection. When conditions ripen (war, economic collapse, demoralized armies), the party seizes power by force, dissolves rival centers of authority, and creates extraordinary organs of repression (Cheka, OGPU, NKVD). Violence is not an accident; it is the instrument of state‑making.
Track B: The “peaceful road.” When a frontal assault is impossible, the party advances by coalition—“united fronts” and “people’s fronts”—to occupy the ministries of interior, justice, information, and defense; to neutralize or capture the police and security services; to merge or outlaw rivals; and to amend constitutions so that elections cannot dislodge the new order. The moment control is consolidated, systematic violence begins: show trials, purges, expropriation, concentration camps, censorship, and the crushing of civil society. The violence is not a temporary wartime expedient; it is structural.
3) Institutions: Party Above Law
In Leninist antifascism, law is instrumental. Courts are subordinated to party “legality”; the press becomes an “agitprop” organ; unions become transmission belts. The constitution is reinterpreted as a facade for party leadership. Separation of powers and independent civil associations are defined as bourgeois myths.
4) Law: Transformational, Irreversible
Legal strategy is revolutionary: use legality to become unremovable, then redefine legality so that the party’s will is the law. “Antifascism” is the bridge from defensive rhetoric to authoritarian consolidation.
III. The Bolshevik Template: From Revolutionary Violence to Institutionalized Coercion
The Bolshevik seizure of power in 1917 is the prototype of Track A. The Provisional Government collapsed under the strain of war; soviets became instruments of party rule; the Constituent Assembly was dispersed by force when it threatened to limit Bolshevik power. The new regime created the Cheka as an extrajudicial weapon for eliminating “class enemies.” The Red Terror followed—hostages, executions, camps, and the suppression of alternative socialist currents (Mensheviks, Socialist Revolutionaries). The Kronstadt uprising of 1921—sailors who had once been Bolshevik allies—was crushed with artillery.
Collectivization and dekulakization in the late 1920s and early 1930s extended state violence into the countryside. The machine destroyed markets, starved regions (most catastrophically in Soviet Ukraine), and produced a surveillance society where denunciations were currency. The Great Terror of 1937–38 annihilated old Bolsheviks and ordinary citizens alike. This was not anti‑fascism; fascism had not yet come to power in Germany. It was the logic of revolutionary state‑building, demonstrating that once the vanguard state exists, violence becomes routine governance.
During World War II the Soviet Union justly fought Nazi Germany. Yet the postwar settlement shows how the regime transformed antifascist victory into empire: the NKVD followed the Red Army across Eastern Europe; parties were merged by force; opponents were tried as “fascists” regardless of their actual politics. The banner of antifascism cloaked the export of one‑party rule.
IV. Spain 1936–1939: Antifascism as a Civil War and a Purge
The Spanish Republic’s Popular Front government was opposed by a military rebellion led by Francisco Franco. International brigades and Soviet support flowed to the Republican side under the flag of antifascism. Inside the Republic, however, Soviet security services and their local allies suppressed independent leftists: the POUM (an anti‑Stalinist Marxist party) was outlawed; its leaders were arrested or killed; anarchist strongholds in Barcelona were attacked during the May Days of 1937. The antifascist camp thus contained a second front: a purge that prioritized party control over pluralist resistance. Spain demonstrates that Leninist antifascism views rivals on the left as an existential threat—often more urgently than it views fascism itself.
V. “People’s Democracies” 1945–1949: The Peaceful Road That Turns Coercive
When Soviet forces occupied Central and Eastern Europe, Moscow did not always stage an immediate Bolshevik‑style seizure. It often pursued Track B—a stepwise “peaceful” transformation.
1) Czechoslovakia
In the immediate postwar years, the National Front combined multiple parties under a coalition that barred those deemed “reactionary.” Communists took key ministries, especially Interior, giving them control of police and security. Propaganda stressed antifascism and reconstruction. In February 1948, a constitutional crisis was used to force non‑communist ministers to resign; mass demonstrations and militias provided pressure; President Beneš capitulated; and Communist leader Klement Gottwald announced a new order. What followed were show trials (Rudolf Slánský and others), purges, and the standardization of a one‑party state.
2) Hungary
Mátyás Rákosi perfected “salami tactics”—slicing away opponents by coalition manipulation, fabricated charges, and security‑service intimidation. Postwar antifascist rhetoric delivered a police dictatorship by 1949.
3) Poland and Romania
Similar patterns appear: coalition governments; security ministries in communist hands; opposition smeared as “fascist” or “anti‑national”; manipulated elections; then the snap of the trap—trials, expropriations, and a constitution that made party rule irreversible.
4) The German Democratic Republic (GDR)
In the Soviet Zone, the KPD and the Social Democratic Party (SPD) were merged—under intense pressure—into the Socialist Unity Party (SED) in 1946. The GDR later branded the Berlin Wall the “Antifascist Protective Rampart” (Antifaschistischer Schutzwall), rhetorically converting a prison wall into a moral shield. The state’s supreme identity was “antifascist,” yet its Stasi ran one of the densest surveillance systems in modern history. Here the Leninist lexicon reaches its apex: antifascism is the language used to justify the suppression of pluralism.
VI. Two Moral Economies of Antifascism
The history supports a schematic contrast:
- General, pluralist anti‑fascism: Aims to preserve a constitutional order; accepts ideological diversity; treats violence as last‑resort defense under law; strives for proportionality.
- Marxist‑Leninist antifascism: Aims to replace the constitutional order; treats pluralism as camouflage; treats violence as constitutive of the new order; uses antifascism as a permanent mobilization myth.
Both may fight fascism. Only one sees liberty under law as the object to be saved.
VII. West Germany’s 1956 Ban of the KPD: Defensive Democracy in Action
1) The Constitutional Premise: A “defensive” Democracy
The Basic Law (Grundgesetz) of the Federal Republic of Germany emerged from the ashes of National Socialism with a sober lesson: an open society must sometimes defend itself against movements that would abolish openness. Article 21(2) authorizes the Federal Constitutional Court to declare a party unconstitutional if its aims or the conduct of its supporters seek to impair or abolish the “free democratic basic order” (freiheitliche demokratische Grundordnung, FDGO) or to endanger the existence of the Federal Republic. This framework had already been applied in 1952 to outlaw the Socialist Reich Party (SRP), a neo‑Nazi formation.
2) Proceedings and Standard of Proof
The federal government petitioned to ban the Communist Party of Germany (KPD) in 1951. Hearings ran from 1954 to 1955; the Court delivered its decision on 17 August 1956. The Court did not criminalize communism as a belief; it assessed the party as an organization: its program, strategy, ties, and conduct. The standard was not mere advocacy of socialism; it was the concrete orientation toward dismantling the FDGO and establishing a dictatorship of the proletariat under foreign (Soviet) influence.
3) Findings
- The KPD’s ideological core was incompatible with the FDGO: it sought to abolish multiparty democracy, independent courts, and fundamental rights, replacing them with proletarian dictatorship.
- Its alignment with the Soviet bloc, and with the SED in East Germany, made it an instrument of a foreign power adversarial to the Federal Republic.
- The Court saw a pattern of aggressive, militant struggle against the constitutional order, even where the KPD used “peaceful” legal tactics. The “peaceful road” was judged a tactic toward an illiberal end.
4) Remedies
The Court declared the KPD unconstitutional; dissolved it; prohibited substitute organizations; and confiscated its assets for the common good. Individuals were not jailed for mere membership; but organizational continuity was barred. The judgment underscored a central axiom: democracy has the right to defend itself when a party’s program aims at its abolition.
5) Significance
The KPD ban exemplifies how a defensive legal order can target organizations—not ideas—whose operational goal is to replace constitutional pluralism with one‑party rule. It was a blunt instrument, controversial then and now; but it was a judicial act grounded in constitutional text, not an executive whim.
VIII. The United States Today: Legal Tools Against Violent Extremism on the Left (and Elsewhere)
1) First Principles of U.S. Law
The United States is constitutionally allergic to party bans. The First Amendment protects speech, association, and assembly; Brandenburg v. Ohio (1969) permits the state to punish advocacy only when it is directed to inciting or producing imminent lawless action and likely to do so. There is no general federal power to designate domestic organizations as “terrorist” in the way the State Department designates foreign terrorist organizations under 8 U.S.C. § 1189. Instead, U.S. authorities prosecute crimes—conspiracy, arson, assault on federal officers, weapons offenses, RICO, the Anti‑Riot Act, and so on—committed by individuals or cells, regardless of ideology.
2) The Current Federal Posture
Since 2025, the Trump administration has announced an aggressive posture toward “Antifa” and other extremist left networks, issuing executive directives to coordinate federal resources against violent actors and those who finance them. The FBI’s Joint Terrorism Task Forces (JTTFs) have been tasked to lead multi‑agency operations; the Treasury Department has been directed to investigate financial networks; and the Department of Homeland Security has reported arrests of individuals it characterizes as “Antifa‑aligned” domestic terrorists. Simultaneously, the White House unveiled an executive action purporting to designate “Antifa” as a domestic terrorist organization and a national‑security memorandum to synchronize efforts against domestic terrorism and organized political violence.
3) Legal Tensions and Practical Effects
Because U.S. law lacks a statutory mechanism for domestic terrorist‑organization designation, executive declarations face legal headwinds. They can, however, drive operational priorities: interagency coordination, intelligence tasking, and the use of existing criminal statutes (conspiracy, material support to enumerated terrorism crimes under 18 U.S.C. § 2339A, if applicable; financial crimes; interstate travel to riot under 18 U.S.C. § 2101). They may also justify financial targeting—for instance, Treasury actions against entities suspected of funding criminal activity, though such moves must satisfy due‑process and statutory predicates. Courts will ultimately arbitrate the limits.
4) Contrast With the KPD Ban
- Source of Authority: West Germany acted via a constitutional court applying an explicit constitutional clause on party unconstitutionality. The U.S. response is driven by the executive within the confines of statutory criminal law and constitutional rights; there is no constitutional power to outlaw a domestic political tendency per se.
- Object of Regulation: The KPD, a formal party, was dissolved. “Antifa,” by contrast, is a diffuse tendency without a formal central organization; U.S. policy therefore targets individual crimes and networks, not a ban of a party.
- Judicial vs. Executive: Germany’s ban was judicial and final in institutional form; the U.S. approach is administrative/operational, contestable in court, and reversible by subsequent administrations.
- Concept of Militant Democracy: Germany’s doctrine permits preemptive defense against parties that would abolish democracy. The U.S. system prefers post‑factum criminal prosecution for violent acts, leaving unpopular ideas and associations largely free unless they cross the imminence threshold to criminal conduct.
5) Risks and Safeguards
Any executive drive against domestic extremism risks overbreadth, politicization, and chilled speech. The remedy in the U.S. tradition is judicial review and the insistence that prosecutions remain tethered to specific criminal acts, not to ideology. This tension is ongoing, and it defines the U.S. difference from the German model.
IX. Strategic Lessons: How Words, Tactics, and Institutions Diverge
- Words: Both camps say “antifascism.” Only one means constitutional continuity. Leninist antifascism weaponizes the word, making it the moral alibi of one‑party domination.
- Tactics: General anti‑fascism maximizes coalition‑building within law. Leninist antifascism treats coalitions as scaffolding to be removed once the party can stand alone.
- Institutions: General anti‑fascism trusts institutions enough to repair them. Leninist antifascism occupies institutions in order to empty and refill them with party content.
- Violence: General anti‑fascism may authorize focused, accountable force to protect the public. Leninist antifascism normalizes coercion as governance and sustains it after victory.
- Law: Militant democracy (Germany) shows one way to defend a constitutional order against a party whose goal is to abolish it—but it entrusts that power to a court under strict criteria. The U.S. approach keeps the focus on individual criminality and treats ideology as protected until it fuses with imminent, likely violence.
X. Historic Examples in Closer Detail
A. The Soviet Union’s “Antifascist” Diplomacy and Domestic Repression (1933–1945)
By the early 1930s, the Comintern adopted Popular Front tactics: communists would ally with liberals and socialists under an antifascist banner. Internationally, Soviet diplomacy used antifascism to gain recognition and alliances against Nazi Germany. Domestically, however, the USSR doubled down on coercion: the Great Terror peaked even as antifascist rhetoric crested abroad. The coexistence of antifascist appeals and internal terror prefigures postwar practice in Eastern Europe: one language for abroad, another for the inside.
B. The Spanish Civil War Revisited: NKVD Methods Inside an Antifascist Camp
The suppression of the POUM and the assault on anarchist strongholds were not tragic side‑effects; they were steps toward monopolizing the security apparatus. Soviet advisors insisted upon political policing as a condition of aid. The Republican coalition’s war effort thus yoked military defense to a program of internal ideological purification—a rehearsal of Track B logic under war conditions.
C. Czechoslovakia’s Show Trials as a Post‑Victory Logic
The Slánský trial (1952) manufactured treason from intra‑party rivalry. Public confessions, scripted by security services, created a myth of hidden fascists and Zionists inside the party. “Antifascism” was deployed not against fascists, but against inconvenient communists—evidence that once the party owns the courts, antifascism becomes a universal solvent for political enemies.
D. The GDR’s “Antifascist Protective Rampart”
A wall that keeps citizens captive is rebranded as a shield against fascists. The move captures the entire Leninist semiotic: rename coercion as protection, and the instruments of control acquire moral glamour. Meanwhile, Stasi files thicken, informers proliferate, and the party’s monopoly on truth turns neighbors into surveillance nodes.
E. Italy and France: When Leninist Antifascism Fails to Capture the State
In postwar Italy and France, powerful communist parties invoked antifascism but did not capture the state. Where constitutional pluralism proved resilient—backed by strong civil societies and competitive elections—Leninist antifascism could not execute Track B to completion. The result was decades of propaganda warfare and episodic street violence, but no one‑party state.
XI. The Juridical Mindset: From “Militant Democracy” to “Criminal Law First”
Germany’s Lesson
The KPD ban teaches a narrow but consequential lesson: a democracy can erect legal tripwires for organizations that openly seek to replace it with a dictatorship. The price is high (party bans chill political experimentation), but Germany built safeguards: only the Constitutional Court may ban; the standard is the aims and conduct of the organization; and the measure is organizational (dissolution, asset seizure), not a mass criminalization of belief.
The U.S. Lesson
The American approach prizes over‑inclusion in speech protection and under‑inclusion in organizational bans. The system trusts juries and criminal codes more than administrative proscriptions of ideology. Executive initiatives may surge in response to waves of violence, but the baseline remains: ideas are free; crimes are not. Whether this model can manage decentralized violent networks in an era of viral mobilization is an open strategic question—but it is the constitutional baseline.
XII. Conclusion: Keep the Meanings Separate
When we speak of anti‑fascism, we should be precise. The term has two lineages. One is the civic defense of a constitutional order against authoritarian ultranationalism—a project that can unite liberals, conservatives, social democrats, and non‑Marxist socialists in an avowedly pluralist coalition. The other is the Marxist‑Leninist project, which treats antifascism as a tactical bridge to a one‑party state, arriving by revolution or by a “peaceful” takeover that culminates in extraordinary courts, censorship, purges, and state violence.
The law has confronted these projects differently. West Germany—scarred by dictatorship—armed its constitutional court with the power to ban parties that seek to abolish the democratic order, and used it against the KPD in 1956. The United States, wary of state power over ideology, wages its fights through criminal law and executive coordination, recently intensified against violent left‑wing networks in operations that test the boundary between security and liberty. The contrast is instructive: militant democracy versus criminal‑law constitutionalism.
The imperative is to keep the meanings separate. If we let the Leninist tradition monopolize the word “antifascism,” we abandon the language of civic defense to a project that historically subverted democracy in its name. If we confuse executive crackdowns with constitutional bans, we risk eroding the legal culture that distinguishes crimes from ideas. A free society must be ready to fight fascists—and to resist those who would, under antifascism’s banner, replace the republic with a new despotism. The harder task is to do both at once: to be militant in defense of the constitution, and militant in defense of the rights that make such a constitution worth defending.